Since the ejection
from the throne and subsequent beheading of Charles I at the end of
the English Civil War in 1649, the hegemonic balance between monarchy
and Parliament had created a political seesaw entirely unprecedented
in the context of British history. On one side were the Whigs, the
reform movement in Parliament that emerged as a united party in clear
opposition to Charles I's son, the emponymously titled Charles II,1
following the restoration of the monarchy in 1660.2
On the other side was the monarchy itself and its supporters in
Parliament, colloquially known as the Tories, who likewise formed an
official and united political front in support of King James II's
right to inherit the throne in spite of his confessed Catholicism.3
The relatively free exchange and formulation of political ideas in
17th century England was in stark contrast to the
monarchical absolutism being practiced on the European continent by
the likes of Louis XIV in France, and Peter the Great in Russia.
Politically dissident opinions abounded, and the toleration of such
open dissent is not only what made England unique, it's what lended a
great amount of momentum to theories of Parliamentary supremacy which
ultimately culminated in the slow formation of modern democratic
institutions. It can be argued, as well, that this open dissidence
and continued friction between Parliament and King, having reached
its absolute crescendo with the forced abdication of James II in
1688, is the moment which forever altered historical trajectory
toward what ultimately resulted in political modernity and global
industrialisation. However, old habits die hard, and history is a
lense through which all events fade to give way to others in slow
succession. Although a revolution in the long run, the so-called
“Glorious Revolution” of 1688-92 was an accidental harbinger of
what one might call “progress,” though it found its genuine and
immediate purpose largely in religiously sectarian intolernace.
Most have
seen a reflection of the ideal revolutionary attitude of 17th
century England in the writings of John Locke, who once famously
wrote, “And no Government will be able long to subsist, if the
People may set up a new Legislative, whenever they take offence at
the old one. To this, I Answer: Quite the contrary. People are not so
easily got out of their old Forms, as some are apt to suggest. They
are hardly to be prevailed with to amend the acknowledg'd Faults, in
the Frame they have been accustom'd to. And if there be any Original
defects, or adventitious ones introduced by time or corruption[,]
'tis not an eas[y] thing to get them changed, even when all the World
sees there is an opportunity for it.”4
In this statement, he may have been prophetic; in part, he may have
been referring to the contrast between the atmosphere of absolutism
on the Continent and the constitutional monarchy so commonplace in
British life. But he was also describing as well as foreshadowing
events of the day and what was still to come, having written his two
treatises on government originally as justification for resistance to
King Charles II (r. 1660-1685),5
but which were later published as a defence of the
self-aggrandizingly titled “Glorious Revolution” beginning in
1688.6
In an intellectual
climate heavily influenced by Aristotle, as well as Plato's 'perfect
world of forms,' it's understandable how a spectating thinker of the
time would sink into a cynical evaluation of facts based on immediate
observation. Alternatively, an inversely over-optimistic evaluation
was just as common, as the effect of Plato's perfect forms was
political utopianism, the expectations of which were often
unceremoniously crushed by reactionaries or simple fact. The
resulting dissapointment—or, more often, despair—of great and
defeated expectations were reconciled by many through the available
remedy of religious dogma, or thoroughly faced, philosophized upon,
and accepted by a very gilded few. John Locke, as quoted in the
second paragraph, had a sense of political realism. He understood
that the course of events were beyond any single persons control, and
that any explicit 'revolution' was, more often than not, simply
occurring to retain a certain circumstance and all the prejudice and
pride that go with it. Yet at the same time his realism seemed to
project a commentary cognizant and accepting of this central
contradiction, he still found himself on the revolutionary side of
history, having fostered a very close relationship with noted Whig
politician Anthony Ashley Cooper, better known as the Earl of
Shaftesbury, as his personal physician during the 1660's.7
This is enough to understand why political gravity, coupled with his
faculties as a philosopher, brought him to believe in the supremacy
of Parliament over a reigning monarch. He became, through his
connections, one of the most outspoken voices in support of the
Whigs, with his works on government gaining comprehensive popularity
throughout the British Isles at the time of the revolution and giving
further intellectual momentum to the ascendent counter-narrative of
limited government.8
This
counter-narrative, however, proved to be less revolutionary, and more
of a watershed moment in the slow historical fade to modern
democracy. The usurpation of the throne from James II to William of
Oranje effected by Parliament was done in response to James finally
siring a male heir, who was baptised a Catholic. James had also
incurred the wrath of Parliament in prior years when he advocated for
tolerance of Catholics and Protestant dissenters, granting both the
right of public worship as well as the ability to hold civil and
military office.9
This ecumenical attitude infuriated the Whigs, who, upon taking joint
power with the new King, implemented a series of draconian laws which
once again barred Catholics and dissenters from public worship,
public office (including running to become a Parliamentary MP),10
and a myriad of other prohibitions designed to humiliate, harass, and
oppress the “papists,” a derogatory term used to refer to
Catholics during and after the English Reformation. In the English
Bill of Rights, for example, it is added as a refrain that “it hath
pleased Almighty God to make the glorious instrument of delivering
this kingdom from popery [Catholicism] and arbitrary power.”
Enshrined as law alongside such famous and fatefully significant
precedents as, “[t]hat election of members [to] Parliament ought to
be free,” and “[t]hat excessive bail ought not to be required,
nor excessive fines imposed, nor cruel and unusual punishments
inflicted,” was “that all and every person and persons that is,
are or shall be reconciled to ... [the] Church of Rome, or shall
profess the popish religion, or shall marry a papist, shall be
excluded and be for ever incapable to inherit, possess or enjoy the
crown and government of this realm”.11
The Bill of Rights also enshrined, rather ironically, the tenets of
John Locke's constitutional theory of government, severely limiting
regal authority and adding a rudimentary form of checks and balances
to the British political system. The reigning monarch was no longer
above the law, but was also now a subject of its universal authority
and application.12
Parliament acted as kingmaker, and defined the parameters of the
debate.
In 1689, the same
year as the passing of the Bill of Rights, Locke penned “A Letter
Concerning Toleration.” Addressing it to an anonymously “Honored
Sir,”13
he makes an argument that asserts the separation of church and state.
He also writes that tolerance for differing religious dispositions
will bring greater peace, as most civil unrest roots from an
inevitable resistance to persecution and repression.14
The fear of the time, however, was of a Catholic takeover of England.
The collective spiritual paranoia born of the Reformation was of such
a power as to compel King William to officially and comprehensively
disenfranchise Catholics, lest he meet the same fate as his deposed
and universally reviled predecessor. This was not a cultural or
political atmosphere conducive to Locke's sensible and compassionate
message. This message took a very familiar perspective, one in which
modern attitudes on the matter are clearly still reflected.
Modern capitalism
also finds one of its original European catalysts in the Glorious
Revolution. During the decades of political gridlock, when the King
would, at times, neglect to convene Parliament for upwards of 3 to 4
years after he failed to make a convincing argument to secure further
funding,15
there was no governmental oversight or control of economics on a
state-wide basis. Communities were left to fend for themselves, and
unless an entrepreuner could secure a royal patent or privilege,
there was no legal protection that allowed for the safe raising of
capital and subsequent investment in local projects and
infrastructure. The alternative to royal patent was to seek
parliamentary legislation from a local representative MP.16
This was complicated to near-impossibility during the years of 1680
to 1688, when Parliament sat for a grand total of no more than 20
weeks. In contrast, the years from 1689 to 1697 saw Parliament in
session for an entire 53-and-a-half months. With its powers now
enshrined on an equal basis with the monarch, and the limitation of
the King's executive authority to the rule of law, there was no
longer a single individual with the power to interfere in the
judicial branch, bypass Parliament, or unilaterally breach and alter
contracts of private property and the protection of rights thereof.17
When it became clear that Parliamentary government truly did secure
property rights and provided the legal guarantee of all financial and
economic contracts being honoured in good faith, a very familiar
market began to emerge and expand. In his essay on how the events of
1688-92 inevitably precipitated the Industrial Revolution of the 19th
century, John Beckett writes: “[t]he commercial and financial
revolutions brought new problems in the organisation of overseas
trade and the mechanisms of public credit, and arising from these
concerns came a succession of bills to establish merchant companies,
restrict the import of foreign luxuries, regulate the market in
stocks, and improve the law in relation to the collection of debt,
the declaration of bankruptcy and the pursuit of small claims.
Parliament was now a forum in which MPs could debate issues of
substance, often with a bearing on their constituencies, in the
context of legislation. It is hardly surprising to find a rapid
increase in legislative initiatives post-1689.”18
Both local and international markets, given these protections,
expanded exponentially. This growth never ceased, and instead
continued to gather momentum through the centuries, giving us modern
industry, credit, transportation, infrastructure, and technology, to
name only a few. In fact, we are part and product of this very
momentum, bearing the fruits of its process and effects.
Rome wasn't built
in a day; nor was considered modernity achieved in any single
technological innovation, philosophical consideration, spiritual
revelation, or political revolution. History is the sum of its parts.
Anything less, and it isn't the whole story. The Glorious Revolution
definitively ended any push for absolutism in England. It also
kickstarted global parlimentarianism, which subsequently led to the
birth of modern democracy and political institutions. It set the
precedent of the Bill of Rights, which, along with the works of John
Locke, inspired the American Declaration of Independence.19
But Locke wasn't incorrect in his assertion that old habits are hard
to kill, even when we all see an opportunity for progress. As
historian Kenan Malik notes, “[t]he Whigs, the party of
parliamentary democracy, the party from which the English liberal
tradition developed, were also the party of anti-Catholic bigotry.”20
The doubled-edged sword of hypocrisy and power continues to beg the
question: what are we actually thinking of when we consider
“progress?”
1 2015.
"Whig." Funk & Wagnalls New World Encyclopedia 1p. 1.
Funk & Wagnalls New World Encyclopedia, EBSCOhost .
2 2015.
"Restoration." Funk & Wagnalls New World Encyclopedia
1p. 1. Funk & Wagnalls New World Encyclopedia, EBSCOhost.
3 Oxford
Dictionaries. 2015. 'Definition Of "Tory" In English From
The Oxford Dictionary'.
4 Locke,
John. 1689. 'Right Of Revolution: John Locke, Second Treatise'.
Press-Pubs.Uchicago.Edu.
http://press-pubs.uchicago.edu/founders/documents/v1ch3s2.html.
5 2015.
"Charles II." Funk & Wagnalls New World
Encyclopedia 1p. 1. Funk & Wagnalls New World Encyclopedia,
EBSCOhost.
6 Sparknotes.
2015. 'Sparknotes: Locke's Second Treatise On Civil Government:
Context'. http://www.sparknotes.com/philosophy/locke/context.html.
7 Anstey,
Peter R., and Lawrence M. Principe. "John Locke and the Case of
Anthony Ashley Cooper." Early Science & Medicine 16,
no. 5 (October 2011): 379-503. Academic Search Complete, EBSCOhost.
8 Malik,
Kenan. 2013. 'John Locke And The Not-Quite-Glorious Revolution'.
Pandaemonium.
9 Kidner,
Frank L, Maria Bucur, Ralph Mathisen, Sally McKee, and Theodore R
Weeks. 2014. Making Europe.
(Independence, KY: Wadsworth
Cengage Learning), 486.
10 The
Avalon Project. 2008. 'English Bill Of Rights, 1689'.
11 The
Avalon Project. 2008. 'English Bill Of Rights, 1689'.
12 Lewis,
Thomas T. 2015. "English Bill of Rights." Salem Press
Encyclopedia Research Starters.
13 Locke,
John. 1689. A Letter Concerning Toleration. Ebook. 1st ed.,
3.
14 Locke,
John. 1689. A Letter Concerning Toleration. Ebook. 1st ed.,
6-14.
15 Beckett,
John. 2014. "The Glorious Revolution, Parliament, and the
Making of the First Industrial Nation."
Parliamentary History
(Wiley-Blackwell) 33, no. 1: 36-53. Historical Abstracts with Full
Text, EBSCOhost, 37.
16 Beckett,
John. 2014. "The Glorious Revolution, Parliament, and the
Making of the First Industrial Nation." Parliamentary History
(Wiley-Blackwell) 33, no. 1: 36-53. Historical Abstracts with Full
Text, 38.
17 Beckett,
John. 2014. "The Glorious Revolution, Parliament, and the
Making of the First Industrial Nation." Parliamentary History
(Wiley-Blackwell) 33, no. 1: 36-53. Historical Abstracts with Full
Text, 39.
18 Beckett,
John. 2014. "The Glorious Revolution, Parliament, and the
Making of the First Industrial Nation." Parliamentary History
(Wiley-Blackwell) 33, no. 1: 36-53. Historical Abstracts with Full
Text, 39.
19 Powell, Jim et al. 2015. 'John Locke: Natural Rights To Life,
Liberty, And Property | Foundation For Economic Education'. Fee.Org.
20 Malik,
Kenan. 2013. 'John Locke And The Not-Quite-Glorious Revolution'.
Pandaemonium.
No comments:
Post a Comment